Wednesday, December 7, 2016

Conscientious Objection and the Constitution

Within the First Amendment to the United States Constitution lies the Free Exercise Clause and the Establishment Clause. The amendment states, “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof…”, The first two clauses of the First Amendment are the clauses that I wish to investigate. These two clauses have been of much debate since their inception. Throughout the history of the United States, the courts and congress have put a special eye on these two clauses, due to the diverse range of religious beliefs that US citizens have.
These beliefs and the two clauses have historically resulted in granting those with religious beliefs, exemptions to certain laws of the United States. Examples of Supreme Court cases in which exemptions are being sought include: West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette (319 U.S. 624, 1943), Sherbert  v. Verner (374 U.S. 398, 1963), and Cantwell v. Connecticut (310 U.S. 296, 1940); each case deals with how a religious conviction can collide with societal norms. The West Virginia case involves a free exercise claim that children who practice faith under the denomination of Jehovah’s Witnesses should not have to recite the Pledge of Allegiance, at first the claim was rejected, but the Supreme Court eventually ruled in favor of the Jehovah’s Witnesses. The West Virginia case seems quite simple from a modern prospective, no one is being injured by a few Jehovah’s Witnesses not participating in the Pledge of Allegiance. Cases such as Sherbert that involve more substantive implications to society are more confusing; the intersection between the Free Exercise Clause, Establishment Clause, and Free Speech Clause also creates more confusion.
The confusion is further exacerbated by Thomas Jefferson’s idea of “a wall of separation between church and State”, yet we see evidence of the other side, Accommodationists, such as government grants given to church run prison programs (Eisgruber and Sager 16). The Accommodationists vs. Separationists ideologies create inconsistencies within US court systems that lead to arbitrary decisions based on Accomodationist or Separationist ideologies. Jefferson's words are taken as constitutional law instead of his own private view on the First Amendment. Eisgruber and Sager point out inconsistencies “that require government to both grant religion privileges and to impose upon it special restrictions—so that, for example, the government must provide wealthy property-owning churches with exemptions not enjoyed by other landholders, but the government cannot allow poor churches to share in nondiscriminatory subsidy programs that benefit other charitable or (secular) providers” (Eisgruber and Sager 18). 
The special privilege that is sometimes granted to religious groups because the group thinks that its Free Exercise of its religion is being infringed can highlight the dichotomy between exemptions granted to religious and nonreligious groups. One such case that highlighted this dichotomy, yet sought to disestablish the dichotomy, was the United States v. Seeger case (324 F.2d 173, 1963). The defendants (Seeger) sought conscientious objector status, which had been granted to specific religious groups, such as the Quakers, but had not yet been extended to those who don’t necessarily have a strong religious conviction. The defendants didn’t not believe in God, but instead used reason to justify their stance on not participating in the military. The US government no longer uses conscription as method to enlist individuals into military service; it is currently a voluntary service. Although the courts finally ruled in favor of Seeger, most agree that the statutory language used to come to the decision was strained, mainly the substitution of “Supreme Being” with “God” (Greenawalt 61). With the Supreme Court cases mentioned above as the background, I will argue that exemptions to the constitution should be granted not on the basis of religious convictions, but on the basis of equality and societal limitations. Conscientious objection to military service is one of the most popular of exemptions to the constitution, specifically related to the Vietnam War era draft policy. I will use conscientious objection as an example for explaining the logical framework of granting exemptions based on equality and societal limitations.
The example I will use is granting conscientious objector status to an individual that is currently serving in the military, but does not hold a religious conviction or a nonreligious conviction that amounts to a deeply held belief. Conscientious objector status can be granted to individuals currently serving in the military, but it is a long and arduous process to obtain said status, mainly due to lack of experience today’s military personal have with the process. For example, if an individual is enlisted in the military during peacetime, but after individual has served half the enlisted time, a war is started between the US and x country. The individual in question disagrees with the war, so the individual decides to seek conscientious objector status. This case is seen as a selective objector to war, rather than a full out objector to war. This case differs from the Seeger case because the individual in question does not have a belief that is parallel to the belief in “Supreme Being”, yet the belief is based on reason and humanist ideals. Should the individual be granted conscientious objector status based on nonreligious convictions? I think the answer is yes, but Gillette v. United States case stated that selective objection to war was not an exemption the court could make (401 U.S. 437, 1971).
Military personal are required to sign a contract upon entering the military, while most other job sectors do not require contracts. Why is that so? The contract is the current device used to prevent would-be objectors from “quitting” the military like most other jobs in the civilian world. Another question to ask is if the military is voluntary, then why is it also not voluntary to quit? Of course, there is questions related to treason, espionage, and leaking of classified information. If a former military service member was found to be involved with the above activity, then they would be prosecuted, so shouldn’t the “quitter” be treated the same? The amount of societal damage would need to be addressed, but I think the damage would not cause unmanageable side effects.
Does one need to articulate or hold their beliefs at a level akin to say believing in Jesus Christ in order to be granted conscientious objector status? Couldn’t a person disagree with drone warfare tactics of the current military, yet agree with pre-drone warfare tactics? The person would be committed to protecting the country, but not by means of drone use. This belief doesn’t seem to be held at the same level as a conscientious object to all war would hold. A more clarifying question would be, can an individual seek resignation from a military position based on self-interest rather than a moral claim? This level of personal autonomy is granted in other parts of our society, but has not yet been granted to those wishing to resign from military service. Greenawalt suggests that understanding how high an individual’s opposition to act and if it the unwillingness to act qualifies as “conscientious” is impossible (Greenawalt 67).
Articulating a person’s level of conscientiousness objection to military is difficult to define, and therefore difficult for congress or judges set a boundary at which exemptions can be granted or not granted. Instead, exemptions should be granted by looking at the societal damage said exemption would cause, along with looking at the equality of the exemption. If the military is to be treated as a civilian job, then exemptions are not even necessary. Would treating military jobs as civilian jobs create unmanageable societal damage? Citizens are forced to pay war taxes by threat of jail time, i.e., all citizens that make income above the established poverty line are required to pay (war) taxes. If citizens refuse to pay taxes based on war, this could cause massive amounts of societal damage, and citizens are currently doing this, legally (by not making above the minimum taxable income) and illegally. If an exemption was granted to citizens unwilling to pay war taxes; this would cause societal damage. I mention this as an example of an exemption that could presumable cause extreme societal damage.
Military service is voluntary, objections to military service are already granted to religious and nonreligious persons (albeit only for all war objectors), draft policy no longer exists, and classification of who is a conscientious objector is impossible; these are four reasons I explained above that provide evidence to grant exemption to selective conscientious objectors. I believe equating civilian and military operations equally will cause little societal damage and effectively create a more equitable situation for members of society. Questions might still arise about security of operating in this manner, but I believe the existing system could handle the effects of this change.
References:
Eisgruber, C.L. and Sager, L.G. Religious Freedom and the Constitution. Harvard University Press: 2007.

Greenawalt, K. Religion and the Constitution: Volume 1 Free Exercise and Fairness. Princeton University Press: 2006.

Sunday, September 11, 2016

Sitting up Straight

Ross Gay said, in my paraphrased logic, don't focus on an idea when approaching the subject of poem or prose, let it come to you, let it hit you on the nose as you walk down the the snow laden street. Of course this was good advice for someone who finds rare motivation in a wood slat covered coffee shop, you know the one that was in the whole-in-the-wall location, ran by that cool guy with the thick rimmed glasses. 

So, when I approach writing a poem, the motivation usually comes after a mediocre pourover and a slight build-up of that gooey substance on the corner of my lips. Or, it could come after I reject the bullshit academia assignment only meant to interest those in Academia. Then, I start with notes, with a quick glance over at an unexpected female stare. This only lasts a moment. 

Not for you

That split second,
I look over at, 
at you, unabashed
our eyes meet
cosmic clouds crashing down
stale, reservoir coffee
on my lips,
madness no, lunacy

Could this ever work?

Not wishing, 
Not dreaming, 
living
Bye.

-----Of course, the structure is all fucked, the timing is off, whose wouldn't be after listening to the dull machine noise of your roommate's window unit AC. The "poem" above is inscribed on an overly thick piece of notebook paper, miniature style. I thought about giving it to the female that inspired me, but she left. That's OK, I don't need to speak to every person that happens to look back at me. 

The other day I had a "look back at me" moment in the dungeon layer of the building I frequent for those academia classes about academia. I won't seek to describe her face, but her stance was..well, typical. One hand gripping her iPhone, the other tensed up waiting to respond. Most of her wait resting on her right leg. She was waiting for something, and outside the bathrooms. I walked towards her, looking directly at her, our eyes met; no, it wasn't one of those magical eye meeting moments. It wasn't a glance, it was a full stare, almost for the whole length of the hallway. I proceeded to the men's restroom, now that you have to define which restroom you are going to. I was going to say hi when I walked out, but she was gone, and I don't remember her face, just the dark brown eyes and olive skin. I ponder that stare, it was atypical, unlike the typical cellphone marriage. We were both unafraid to sustain the 15 second stare, I lost. Her eye's are special, not special in the romantic sort of way, just special because they looked back for 15 seconds. Those 15 second eyes lead to those 15 minute retrospective ojos. Los ojos que nunca, probablemente, voy a ver otra vez, y tengo estar bien con eso, tengo que pasar por todos los momentos, no borrar, no olvidar, solo esperar. Thoughts seem to have more clarity when they pass both through English and Spanish. No puedo preguntar, what if.  

In all of this, I am seeking for understanding of time, for understanding of why I almost cried over the death of a friend's brother that I never met. I bet it was the pain I saw in his face, and also the pain I also in the face of another friend who has to slowly say goodbye to his father. That hurt, that extreme empathy. Not everybody feels the same way even if we were sitting in that hallowed out room, waiting to be filled with empathy, apathy, sadness, openness, and hopefully the misunderstood. 
I will continue my search.